19 May 2025
Brief Notes on Various Topics – 47
1. I’ve been spending time rereading Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Killing Animals and I think it is a very fine example of a Platonic treatise. Porphyry integrates many aspects of Platonic philosophy in his extended apology for vegetarianism. He does this by placing the practice of vegetarianism in the context of both Platonic ethics and Platonic metaphysics.
What impresses me this time around is how Porphyry understands the necessity of ethical ascetic practice for purification to take place and for the divine ascent to the One to happen. This differs from many spiritual groups I have observed over the decades. There is a strong tendency in some groups to minimize ethical practice. By ‘ethical practice’ I mean the commitment to ethical guidelines and regulations such as those found in traditional Dharmic traditions. In Dharmic traditions these are usually encoded in precepts that outline these ethical commitments such as non-harming, non-stealing, refraining from alcohol, and so forth. In Platonism the ethical regulations are scattered among different dialogues but the two dialogues that stand out in this regard are Phaedo and The Republic.
The way I look at this is that the ethical precepts, which are all restraints on types of behavior, function as a kind of vessel, or bowl, or goblet, for holding the practice of contemplation, or creating the context for contemplation. Many Westerners, it seems, have the view that contemplation by itself is sufficient for realization and that adherence to a set of ethical restraints are not causally related to the insights and realizations that the practice of contemplation offers. But Porphyry makes a direct connection between the practice of ethical restraints, such as vegetarianism, and effecacious contemplation; a point Porphyry makes several times in his work On Abstinence.
What happens when contemplation is done outside of the context of ethical restraints? What happens is that the insights, energy, and realizations that contemplation brings in such a context become value free experiences; and being value free they can be used for any purpose. This resembles learning how to swing a baseball bat. Someone who has learned how to swing a bat in the context of the rules of the baseball game will bring his fellow teammates much pleasure and fans will also be happy about such skill. But someone who has no interest in the rules of baseball can use the bat to break a window, or even to break some bones. The skill of swinging a baseball bat is a value free skill and how it is used depends on the context in which that skill is used.
I am suggesting that contemplation outside of the context of ethical restraints and asceticism is similarly problematic. If looked at in this way, it helps us to understand why some individuals who have meditated for many years, and can guide others in the practice of meditation or contemplation, are sometimes examples of ethically challenged lives; they break the window of their lives and leave behind them much suffering. In extreme cases this can result in a practitioner of contemplation or meditation encouraging mayhem. Unfortunately, this has been observed more than once.
There is a feeling that this kind of analysis has to be wrong because contemplation is innately transformative. The conclusion would follow, then, that someone who behaves badly could not be an actual contemplative, that they must not really understand what contemplation means. Beyond the fact that this is a classic ‘no true Scotsman’ fallacy, I think this kind of analysis, or view, of contemplation underestimates the ability of insight and spiritual experiences to be used in a value-free way. There are, for example, corporations who want their employees to meditate because their employees are more focused and therefore more productive when they meditate; this is a good example of value free spiritual practice.
My overall point about Porphyry is that his understanding of Platonism is wholistic; I mean that Porphyry views the practices of purification and ethical restraint as foundational for Platonic practice and it is upon this foundation that contemplation takes place and blossoms. Or to return to the previous metaphor, the practices of ethical restraint are the vessel which allows the practitioner to drink from the nectar of contemplation; without that vessel the realizations of contemplative practice will spill onto the ground and disappear from sight.
2. Plato returns to his hermitage after a long morning walk. The hermitage is located in the hills between two valleys. There are a lot of oak trees and the foliage is mostly grass. There is a creek running through the landscape that flows out of the valley at one end.
Plato sits at a table where the notebook he is writing in lies open. After getting comfortable Plato continues his writing. He is writing another dialogue which, he thinks, he might finish in another thousand years, perhaps two thousand.
3. I have for a long time had difficulty with the idea of ‘matter’ in Platonic philosophy. As I have said in a previous post, perhaps more than one, I’m not convinced that matter is a necessary concept in Platonism; by that I mean I think it might be possible to present Platonism without having to resort to the idea of matter. I’m not confident about this, though.
These thoughts returned to my mind because I was reading John Dillon’s essay “Ennead III.5: Plotinus’ Exegesis of the Symposium Myth”. In this essay (which I found complex and not always easy to follow) comments about matter on pages 76-77 (the book is Perspectives on Plotinus). Dillon quotes Plotinus at III 5.9.49-53, and comments on the quote, “And so we have it – without qualification, it seems – Penia is Matter." Looking up ‘penia’ I found it means lack or deficiency. So matter is a kind of deficiency or a lack. Later Dillon suggests that matter is in some way associated, or ‘stands for’, the ‘irrational element in Soul’.
But I remain puzzled. It’s not clear to me why we need the idea of matter to explain the irrational element in Soul, or why a lack or a deficiency requires the presence of matter. For example, a fire generates heat. The heat diminishes with distance. If someone sits close to a fire they will feel comfortably warm, even in winter. If someone sits across the room, the heat from the fire will have diminished; that is to say there is a lack of heat for those sitting across the room from the fire. And if someone is outside, the lack of heat from the fire at the hearth is so great they will likely not notice the presence of the heat from the fire. It does not seem to me that anything additional is needed to explain the heat diminishing with distance; this kind of observation indicates that such diminishment is part of what ‘distance’ means.
Metaphysically, the greater the metaphysical distance from the One, the less unity a thing has. But it is distance that is determinative here.
It is likely that I am missing something but as a thought experiment, what would Platonism look like without matter?
4. When does a sunrise begin? When does a flower start to bloom? It is not a simple thing to make these kinds of determinations.
Similarly, spiritual insights grow in us in ways that, for the most part, are undramatic and not recognized when they first appear in our minds and hearts.
5. There is a book on Porphyry by Aaron P. Johnson called Religion and Identity in Porphyry of Tyre, Cambridge University Press. I purchased it over a year ago, maybe two years ago. Because my interest in Porphyry has been rekindled I took it down from the shelf and have started to read it. The book is academic, but still accessible for those with some background in Late Classical Platonism. There are some technical issues, such as variations in the taxonomy of the divine and how the different taxonomies are related to different views on Platonist practice, which it is not always clear as to why the topic is significant. But I find the if I slow my reading pace and take in what the author has to offer, the topics and their relationships come into focus.
But what I found very helpful is a translation of the fragments of Porphyry. These fragments are collected in the closing section of the book. Many of Porphyry’s books survive only in quotations from other classical authors who commented on Porphyry’s views. These quotations are the sources for the fragments. They are listed by topic and author. For example, there are a lot of quotes from Porphyry that are found in various works by Saint Augustine, many more than I was aware of. I find these quotes illuminating and even though I know they are fragments, there is enough of Porphyry in his surviving books to get a sense of where these quoted fragments might fit into Porphyry’s overall thought.
Recently I came across a paper at academia (dot) edu on what were the sources for Augustine’s understanding of Platonism. The paper is titled “Augustine between Plotinus and Porphyry: A Possible Answer to the Problem of the Identity of the Platonicorum Libri” by Paolo Di Leo. The paper discusses different views as to what Augustine read and studied when he was involved with Platonism; the author says that some scholars advocate for the primary source being Plotinus, others argue for Porphyry, and others for both. It’s an interesting paper.
From the listing of fragments where Augustine is quoting Porphyry, I can see why some scholars would side with Porphyry as the primary source. But I don’t know enough about Augustine to make an intelligent evaluation of this discussion.
It is somewhat surprising, pleasantly surprising, how influential Porphyry has been in the history of Platonism. While I wouldn’t say that Porphyry is as influential as Plotinus, I’m gradually seeing that Porphyry’s writings have had a big impact on Platonism over the centuries. For example, Porphyry’s On Abstinence had a significant impact on the Renaissance understanding of Platonism (see Renaissance Vegetarianism: The Philosophical Afterlives of Porphyry’s On Abstinence by Cecilia Muratori which I previously reviewed on this blog).
It's paradoxical that Porphyry, the author of Against the Christians, seems to have had an impact on Augustine and how Augustine understood Platonism. But perhaps the anti-Christian work of Porphyry was something Augustine may have felt a need to deal with, and from there Augustine became more familiar with what Porphyry had to say on other topics. For example, both Porphyry and Augustine were ascetics and valued what I call the Ascetic Ideal; this would be a strong connection.
If you are interested in Porphyry, I recommend Religion and Identity. I think you will find the thought of the author, as well as the translations of the fragments, to be helpful in studying this significant Platonist writer and practitioner.
6. I think that one thing that links Dharmic traditions with Platonism is the way both Dharmic traditions and Platonism have a commitment to ethical teachings whose foundations are shared. I am referring to the teachings on non-harming found in Jainism, Buddhism, Yoga, and Platonism. In Dharmic traditions non-harming, or Ahimsa, is often the first ethical Precept or Vow. All other vows can be understood to be the application of Ahimsa to specific contexts of human life.
While in Dharmic traditions, as mentioned above, the principle of Ahimsa, or non-harming, is found in its placement at the head of lists of ethical precepts, commitments, or vows. Platonism, as far as I know, did not generate that kind of document; that is to say, there is no listing of precepts in Platonism in the way one finds in Buddhism, Jainism, and Yoga. This means that the teachings on non-harming are scattered in various works of Platonism from the Dialogues (see, for example, Crito) to Porphyry’s treatise On Abstinence. There are also references to non-harming as being an ancient teaching that Platonism has inherited, though sources are not specifically mentioned (I think it is likely that they are Pythagorean and Orphic).
But the foundational nature of non-harming for Platonism and for Dharmic traditions is, I think, recognizably similar. I say ‘similar’ rather than ‘the same’ because exactly how non-harming, or Ahimsa, works has its differences among Dharmic traditions (for example, the role that intention plays in an act of harming differs among Dharmic traditions). It is, therefore, to be expected that there will be some differences in how Platonism applies non-harming/Ahimsa. One thing I have noticed, which I offer as a tentative observation, is that Platonism seems to place a strong emphasis on non-retaliation as a necessary effect of non-harming; at least that is how I read Crito. Another emphasis in Platonism is how non-harming is linked to the virtue of justice, and from there to the Platonic virtues overall.
But though there are differences, the emphasis on non-harming as such is shared. And I think that sharing is a good reason for considering Platonism to be more closely allied to Dharmic traditions than it is to what modern philosophy has become.