24 February 2024
Strife and Injustice
“Socrates: Injustice, Thrasymachus, causes civil war, hatred, and fighting among themselves, while justice brings friendship and a sense of common purpose. Isn’t that so?
“Thrasymachus: Let it be so, in order not to disagree with you.
“Socrates: You’re still doing well on that front. So tell me this: If the effect of injustice is to produce hatred wherever it occurs, then, whenever it arises, whether among free men or slaves, won’t it cause them to hate one another, engage in civil war, and prevent them from achieving any common purpose?
“Thrasymachus: Certainly.
“Socrates: What if it arises between two people? Won’t they be at odds, hate each other, and be enemies of one another and to just people?
Thrasymachus: They will.
“Socrates: Does injustice lose its power to cause dissension when it arises within a single individual, or will it preserve it intact?
“Thrasymachus: Let it preserve it intact.
“Socrates: Apparently, then, injustice has the power, first, to make whatever it arises in – whether it is a city, a family, an army, or anything else – incapable of achieving anything as a unit, because of the civil wars and differences it creates, and, second, it makes that unit an enemy to itself and to what is in every way its opposite, namely, justice. Isn’t that so?
“Thrasymachus: Certainly.
“Socrates: And even in a single individual, it has by its nature the very same effect. First, it makes him incapable of achieving anything, because he is in a state of civil war and not of one mind; second, it makes him his own enemy, as well as the enemy of just people. Hasn’t it that effect?
“Thrasymachus: Yes.
(Plato, The Republic, translated by G. M. A. Grube, revised by C. D. C. Reeve, Plato: Complete Works, edited by John M. Cooper, Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, 1997, pages 995 and 996, 351d-352a, ISBN: 9780872203495)
“Socrates: Yes, for injustice surely breeds hatred, dissension and fighting among people, whereas justice brings concord and friendship: isn’t that so?
“Thrasymachus: Let it be so, he replied, to avoid my contradicting you.
“Socrates: You are doing well, my friend. But tell me this: if it is the function of injustice to foster hatred wherever it is, when it arises among both free men and slaves, won’t it cause them to hate each other, quarrel and be unable to act in concert?
“Thrasymachus: Indeed, yes.
“Socrates: What if injustice arises between two people? Won’t they quarrel and hate each other and be at odds both with each other as well as with those who are just?
“Thrasymachus: They will, he replied.
“Socrates: But, my dear fellow, what if injustice arises within one person; surely it won’t lose its power, but rather retain it undiminished?
“Thrasymachus: Let’s say it will, he replied.
“Socrates: Does it then appear to have the kind of power that wherever it arises, in a city, a family, an army, or anywhere else, it makes it firstly incapable of cooperation with itself owing to factions and quarrels, and secondly makes it hostile both to itself and to every opponent, including the man who is just? Isn’t that so?
“Thrasymachus: Certainly.
“Socrates: And so, I think, dwelling in a single person it will bring about those very same effects which it naturally produces: it will make him firstly unable to act because of strife and lack of agreement within himself, and secondly he will be hostile both to himself and to those who are just. True?
“Thrasymachus: Yes.”
(Plato, The Republic, translated by Chris Emlyn-Jones and William Preddy, Loeb Classical Library, Plato: The Republic Books 1-5, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 2013, pages 105-107, 351d-352, ISBN: 9780674996502)
1. This passage explains how Plato analyzes topics, such as justice and injustice, by referring to principles that transcend specific appearances. The principle of injustice is the principle of strife. Strife can be observed in nations, city-states, smaller communities, families, and even in individuals.
2. The topic investigated in The Republic is justice and how it manifests in various contexts, as well how justice is thwarted in those various contexts.
3. This passage helps us to understand the allegorical nature of The Republic. There is a strong tendency in modernity to read The Republic as if it is a type of political treatise. Most often I hear people referring to The Republic as a kind of utopia. The view is that Plato was expressing his own political theory in The Republic and that dialogue is the place to go to find out what Plato envisioned as an ideal political organization.
3.1 But this passage suggests otherwise. For one thing Plato specifically suggests that the teachings under discussion (the nature of justice and injustice) are principles that are equally applicable to groups of people of all sizes and types, and even to single individuals. This is because Plato presents justice, and the negation of justice, meaning injustice, as a principle that is instantiated in human interaction. In the case of an individual one can see the principle of justice operating because human beings are not unified; they have conflicting goals, hopes, and fears. The conflicting nature of the human psyche interacts in ways that allow for justice or injustice to manifest; that is to say one can be just towards oneself, or one can act unjustly to oneself.
3.2 What Plato is suggesting is that an individual is a kind of republic and that the functions of an individual are similar enough to the functions of a republic that the philosopher can see that the same principles apply in both cases.
4. This passage assists the reader in understanding why allegory and myth play such an important part in The Republic. It is possible to map an allegory onto multiple situations; situations that might seem to be very different, even to the extent of possessing different natures when looked at only in a surface manner.
5. In Plato allegory (and metaphor, simile, and similar structures) is not just a literary device. Allegory is a mode of philosophical investigation, a mode of reasoning. In Platonism allegory is a necessary tool both for philosophical understanding and for philosophical investigation because it brings our attention through the use of such comparisons to non-sensory realities.
5.1 This use of comparison as structures of reason and inference is part of the earliest Greek philosophy. For example, when Heraclitus says “Everything flows” (Panta rhei) he is pointing to a reality that transcends any specific example. For example, Heraclitus is saying that a boulder flows, even though we do not observe the flowing of the boulder in the way that we observe the flowing of a river. The inferential structure is to take an example of X that can be observed (a flowing river) and then infer that the same reality is present in examples where X cannot be observed through the senses.
5.2 Plato does this with more abstract understanding such as justice and injustice. And Plato’s technique in The Republic is to use complex allegories to illuminate the presence of justice, and injustice, in multiple domains such as the individual psyche, the family, a group of friends, a community such as a city, and so forth. We can infer that justice and injustice are present in humanity as a whole.
5.3 I once saw a debate on Youtube between two people. The host, in arguing for his position, at one point used a simile: “X is like . . . “ His opponent said, “No; I don’t have to respond to that. I only use logic when discussing philosophical issues.” The host didn’t know how to defend his use of simile and simply went on with the discussion.
This illustrates to me how these kinds of structures (allegory, simile, and so forth) have, for the most part, dropped out of the realm of philosophy and are no longer considered to be legitimate arguments. I think this is attributable to the materialism of modernity as a whole; but in the field of philosophy I think this inability to use these ancient philosophical tools is due to the dominance of the analytic tradition and that tradition’s misunderstanding of how words work; this is especially true in the Anglo-Saxon world.
5.4 Allegorical explorations and presentations are necessary because the foundation of Platonic philosophy is that which is ineffable, that which is beyond predication, beyond affirmation or negation. In order to talk about this kind of reality a philosopher can use several strategies: the philosopher can remain silent, the philosopher can use only negations when discussing the ineffable foundations of existence, or the philosopher can use comparisons, meaning to say what the ineffable resembles, what the ineffable is like. What the ineffable is like might be in the form of a metaphor or simile, it might be in the form of an allegory, such as the allegory of the cave, or it might be a mythos, such as what is found in the penultimate section of Phaedo or in the Myth of Er in The Republic or the Myth of Atlantis in Timaeus.
These different strategies for talking about the ineffable have their drawbacks; remaining silent might be taken as aloof or simply posturing, using only negations to talk about the ineffable may lead the listener to think that the ineffable is a sterile and abstract idea that has no content and therefore no connection to anyone’s life, and using structures of comparison such as metaphor and allegory can lead to reifying, or personifying, the ineffable. A good teacher will be aware of these possibilities for misinterpretation and a good reader will also be aware of them and do what the reader can to not misunderstand what is being said.
6. The passage also helps us to understand how The Republic has several layers of meaning; one layer is for a political context, another layer can apply to social situations like a business, military units, and families, and another layer refers to the individual psyche and its conflicting tendencies. This is one of the reasons why The Republic is so powerful and so moving; from our everyday interactions and lives to our commitments to the Way of Philosophy, The Republic is there to guide us, to offer us assistance in our great journey of returning to the ineffable One.
7. Justice is a reflection of the unity of the One. Things like friendship, peace between nations, are instantiations of that sense of unity as it manifests in the material realm. Injustice is a consequence of the separation that is of the nature of the material domain. In this way Plato connects the metaphysical with ordinary activity; Plato perceives ordinary activity in the material world as consequences of our distance from the unity of the One. This is why The Republic is a metaphysical, not political, work. And this is why The Republic’s purpose is to lead us back to that unity which transcends the divisions that injustice brings to our world.