28 April 2025
Brief Notes on Various Topics – 44
1. I’ve been thinking, more like pondering, about the division in Platonism between those who regard the soul as ‘fully descended’ and those who do not regard the soul as fully descended. ‘Descended’ in this context means ‘descended into the material realm from higher realities; either the noetic or the ineffable transcendental of the Good and the One. This division emerged in the late Classical Period; it was one part of various disputes between Porphyry and Iamblichus. The dispute has left a lasting impression on the Platonist tradition. There are those who regard the soul as always resident in the transcendental, exemplified by Plotinus, and there are those who regard the soul as separated from the transcendental, exemplified by Proclus (see the last section of the Elements of Theology).
1.1 I think my recent focus on this unresolved split within Platonism was stimulated at this time by my reading Theurgy and the Soul by Gregory Shaw; Shaw takes the view of Iamblichus and critiques Plotinus on this issue. To be fair, Shaw’s criticism of Plotinus is nuanced in the sense that he points out where Iamblichus likely misunderstood Plotinus. Even so, I think overall that Shaw misrepresents Plotinus, but that’s to be expected from someone like myself who is so dedicated to Plotinus as a guide and an embodiment of transcendent wisdom.
1.2 As I was thinking about this it came to me that the idea of the partial descent of the soul is not an unusual, or eccentric, view within a Platonic context. I think partial descent is something we have all experienced. For example, think of attending a lecture that is introducing a complex topic (perhaps in a classroom context, perhaps online, perhaps in person at a venue). You are interested in the topic but there are parts of the lecture that you don’t understand, while there are other parts that immediately make sense. This is a very common experience when, for example, learning a new language or beginning a branch of mathematics, and so forth. What I want to suggest is that this is an example of a ‘partial descent’ of the topic into one’s mind. When we have this experience, we know that our understanding is partial and that there is more to learn. In a similar way, the partial descent of the soul into matter leaves the soul with only a partial understanding of its own place in the cosmos; more needs to be studied and understood and this is accomplished through renunciation, study, and contemplation.
1.3 There are other examples of partial descent in our experience of the world. When the light of the moon appears in a pond, that is the partial descent of the light of the moon into the pond. In a similar way, the soul can be thought of as analogically the partial descent of the light of the One into the pond of individuated material existence.
1.3.1 Another example, among many that can be chosen, is the material tree as an instantiation of, or emanation from, the form of treeness. Each tree is descended from treeness but the material tree is only a partial representation of treeness. All trees are like that; they have a limited reality here, and a transcendent reality there where treeness resides.
1.4 The partial descent of the soul also resembles the descent of higher, abstract, realities into materiality. The descent of the One, in the sense of Unity, is partial in the material world. The unity of a material being happens because of material beings’ participation in the One, in Unity itself. But the unity of material beings is only a partial unity; if it were a full unity, a full descent of the One into material embodiment, then material beings would be the One itself. The partial unity, or Oneness, of material beings is on display as becoming and begoning. The One, and Noetic realities, do not participate in becoming and begoning, but material beings do and that is why the Oneness of material beings is only a partial Oneness.
1.5 It is my feeling that the idea of the full descent of the soul came into Platonism from Christianity. What I am getting at is that the Christian view of fallen humanity is that because of the fall humans need an intermediary to connect with God because human beings are too sinful to make such a connection on their own. The intermediary for Christians is Jesus who is considered to be fully human and fully Divine, fully God. Because of this complex nature Jesus can save human beings from their fallen condition.
In a similar way, those Late Classical Platonists who argued for the full descent of the soul also argued for intermediaries, plural, consisting of the Gods of the Greek pantheon. Through carefully constructed ritual the practitioner could contact one, or more, of these intermediaries who had the ability to lift the separated and fully descended human soul to noetic, and possibly higher, realms.
I understand that usually those who study the history of Platonism view Platonism and Paganism in the Late Classical period as deeply in opposition to Christianity; but I tend to see them as in significant ways engaged in the same project which in this case is based on the idea of the human soul as fully separated from the transcendental.
1.6 Returning to the context of Platonism and its internal disputes, I think that there has been a tendency to look at this dispute within Platonism in a way that is too analytical; in addition, there is a tendency to use language that is too technical when discussing this issue (too technical in the sense that the language used obscures rather than clarifies). If, instead, we look at this issue through the procedures of analogy and metaphor, particular to our own experience, then the assertion that the soul is not fully descended into the material realm makes intuitive, and logical sense (logical in a Platonic sense) with a clear experiential basis.
2. The history of Platonism gives me the impression of a very malleable tradition. I say that because it seems that Platonism finds it easy to adapt to changing environments so that Platonism does not resist, or does not resist very much, putting on the robes of various other traditions such as Greek Paganism, Skepticism, Judaism, Christianity, Islam, Mathematics, and so forth. Some traditions are highly resistant to this kind of display; Jainism is one example.
I think this is because Platonism regards the material domain as inherently unstable and in constant flux. Looked at in this way I think it makes sense that one would accept the kind of changes and adaptations that Platonism has gone through. The focus of Platonism is on the transcendental which is, from one perspective, ultimate otherness. This ultimate otherness is not to be found here in the material domain; it is there in the transcendental. From this perspective it is not a matter of first importance what robes the tradition wears.
3. There is a social movement which is called ‘Minimalism’. When I say ‘movement’ I don’t mean that Minimalism is very organized or that someone can attain an official certificate of Minimalism. But there are people who act as what I would call guides to a minimalist life.
The movement is strongly devoted to simplifying one’s life by having as few things as possible, cutting back on extraneous things, or things one no longer actually needs. Some Minimalists have very few possessions indeed. Others are more moderate in their minimalism.
The Minimalist movement has a strong aesthetic component to it which some emphasize more than others. I have noticed that there seems to be a Japanese aesthetic influence, which makes sense; and some of those offering Minimalist insights are Japanese.
But there is also a philosophical component. And at times it seems some minimalists are almost taking a vow of poverty. I haven’t run across any explicitly religious content from Minimalists; but there is a kind of sense that many minimalists are turning away from the material world having seen through its false promises. This is often motivated by wanting to have time to do what is important in the life of a minimalist instead of their life being consumed by and wasted on the accumulation of things.
I take all of this as a positive sign. It indicates to me a kind of inchoate spiritual yearning. Perhaps something profound will emerge from this.
4. Brief is the life of a mountain.
5. “. . . and the first requirement for a happy life is to do yourself no injury nor allow any to be done to you by others. Of course, the first half of the requirement presents no great problem; the difficulty lies in becoming strong enough to be immune to injury – and the one and only thing that brings such immunity is complete virtue. The same applies to a state: if it adopts the ways of virtue, it can live in peace; but if it is wicked, war and civil war will plague it.”
(Plato, Laws, translated by Travor J. Saunders, Plato: The Complete Works, edited by John M. Cooper, Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, 1997, page 1491, 829a, ISBN: 9780872203495)
“Now those who live happily must first avoid doing injustice to others and suffering injustice themselves at the hands of others. Of these two, the former is not very difficult, but what is very difficult is acquiring the power that prevents being done injustice – this cannot be completely achieved unless one becomes completely good. This very same thing applies to a city: if it becomes good it lives a life of peace, but it lives a life of external and internal war if it is evil.”
(Plato, Laws, translated by Thomas L. Pangle, The Laws of Plato, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1980, page 219, 829a, ISBN: 0226671100)
5.1 It’s interesting to see that Plato in this passage makes an explicit case for the city and the individual as being kind of mutual analogies for each other (in the passage immediately preceding the one quoted, Plato also asserts this). I think this suggests that the Laws, as is true of most of Plato’s dialogues, is written at multiple levels simultaneously and that the Laws is at one level a guide for how to live a good life.
It's not easy to see this in the long passages where the Laws discusses setting up various bureaus and committees in great detail; at least I find it difficult to see how this applies to my life as an individual. But that is probably due to my own limited understanding.
5.2 It is helpful to see how Plato’s teaching on non-harming, or non-injury, makes an appearance here in his last dialogue. Non-injury, injustice, and non-harming often have the same valence in the dialogues.
5.3 Plato seems to be suggesting that it is possible for a city, which in Plato’s day would mean a city-state which is close to what we mean by a country, can live in peace. At other times in the Laws Plato expresses frustration that there has to be discussion about laws for acts that the three characters in the dialogue find abhorrent or disgusting; but (and you can almost hear the sigh) they have to do so because human beings have tendencies in those directions and they must be dealt with. My conclusion is that Plato likely leans to the view that a City living in peace (both internally and externally) is probably a utopian fantasy.